History & Society

mathematical induction

mathematics
verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

print Print
Please select which sections you would like to print:
verifiedCite
While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies. Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.
Select Citation Style
Feedback
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).
Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

Peano, Giuseppe
Peano, Giuseppe
Related Topics:
induction
proof

mathematical induction, one of various methods of proof of mathematical propositions, based on the principle of mathematical induction.

Principle of mathematical induction

A class of integers is called hereditary if, whenever any integer x belongs to the class, the successor of x (that is, the integer x + 1) also belongs to the class. The principle of mathematical induction is then: If the integer 0 belongs to the class F and F is hereditary, every nonnegative integer belongs to F. Alternatively, if the integer 1 belongs to the class F and F is hereditary, then every positive integer belongs to F. The principle is stated sometimes in one form, sometimes in the other. As either form of the principle is easily proved as a consequence of the other, it is not necessary to distinguish between the two.

The principle is also often stated in intensional form: A property of integers is called hereditary if, whenever any integer x has the property, its successor has the property. If the integer 1 has a certain property and this property is hereditary, every positive integer has the property.

Proof by mathematical induction

An example of the application of mathematical induction in the simplest case is the proof that the sum of the first n odd positive integers is n2—that is, that (1.) 1 + 3 + 5 +⋯+ (2n − 1) = n2 for every positive integer n. Let F be the class of integers for which equation (1.) holds; then the integer 1 belongs to F, since 1 = 12. If any integer x belongs to F, then (2.) 1 + 3 + 5 +⋯+ (2x − 1) = x2. The next odd integer after 2x − 1 is 2x + 1, and, when this is added to both sides of equation (2.), the result is (3.) 1 + 3 + 5 +⋯+ (2x + 1) = x2 + 2x + 1 = (x + 1)2. Equation (2.) is called the hypothesis of induction and states that equation (1.) holds when n is x, while equation (3.) states that equation (1.) holds when n is x + 1. Since equation (3.) has been proved as a consequence of equation (2.), it has been proved that whenever x belongs to F the successor of x belongs to F. Hence by the principle of mathematical induction all positive integers belong to F.

The foregoing is an example of simple induction; an illustration of the many more complex kinds of mathematical induction is the following method of proof by double induction. To prove that a particular binary relation F holds among all positive integers, it is sufficient to show first that the relation F holds between 1 and 1; second that whenever F holds between x and y, it holds between x and y + 1; and third that whenever F holds between x and a certain positive integer z (which may be fixed or may be made to depend on x), it holds between x + 1 and 1.

The logical status of the method of proof by mathematical induction is still a matter of disagreement among mathematicians. Giuseppe Peano included the principle of mathematical induction as one of his five axioms for arithmetic. Many mathematicians agree with Peano in regarding this principle just as one of the postulates characterizing a particular mathematical discipline (arithmetic) and as being in no fundamental way different from other postulates of arithmetic or of other branches of mathematics.

Get a Britannica Premium subscription and gain access to exclusive content. Subscribe Now

Henri Poincaré maintained that mathematical induction is synthetic and a priori—that is, it is not reducible to a principle of logic or demonstrable on logical grounds alone and yet is known independently of experience or observation. Thus mathematical induction has a special place as constituting mathematical reasoning par excellence and permits mathematics to proceed from its premises to genuinely new results, something that supposedly is not possible by logic alone. In this doctrine Poincaré has been followed by the school of mathematical intuitionism which treats mathematical induction as an ultimate foundation of mathematical thought, irreducible to anything prior to it and synthetic a priori in the sense of Immanuel Kant.

Directly opposed to this is the undertaking of Gottlob Frege, later followed by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell in Principia Mathematica, to show that the principle of mathematical induction is analytic in the sense that it is reduced to a principle of pure logic by suitable definitions of the terms involved.

Transfinite induction

A generalization of mathematical induction applicable to any well-ordered class or domain D, in place of the domain of positive integers, is the method of proof by transfinite induction. The domain D is said to be well ordered if the elements (numbers or entities of any other kind) belonging to it are in, or have been put into, an order in such a way that: 1. no element precedes itself in order; 2. if x precedes y in order, and y precedes z, then x precedes z; 3. in every non-empty subclass of D there is a first element (one that precedes all other elements in the subclass). From 3. it follows in particular that the domain D itself, if it is not empty, has a first element.

When an element x precedes an element y in the order just described, it may also be said that y follows x. The successor of an element x of a well-ordered domain D is defined as the first element that follows x (since by 3., if there are any elements that follow x, there must be a first among them). Similarly, the successor of a class E of elements of D is the first element that follows all members of E. A class F of elements of D is called hereditary if, whenever all the members of a class E of elements of D belong to F, the successor of E, if any, also belongs to F (and hence in particular, whenever an element x of D belongs to F, the successor of x, if any, also belongs to F). Proof by transfinite induction then depends on the principle that if the first element of a well-ordered domain D belongs to a hereditary class F, all elements of D belong to F.

One way of treating mathematical induction is to take it as a special case of transfinite induction. For example, there is a sense in which simple induction may be regarded as transfinite induction applied to the domain D of positive integers. The actual reduction of simple induction to this special case of transfinite induction requires the use of principles which themselves are ordinarily proved by mathematical induction, especially the ordering of the positive integers, and the principle that the successor of a class of positive integers, if there is one, must be the successor of a particular integer (the last or greatest integer) in the class. There is therefore also a sense in which mathematical induction is not reducible to transfinite induction.

The point of view of transfinite induction is, however, useful in classifying the more complex kinds of mathematical induction. In particular, double induction may be thought of as transfinite induction applied to the domain D of ordered pairs (x, y) of positive integers, where D is well ordered by the rule that the pair (x1, y1) precedes the pair (x2, y2) if x1 < x2 or if x1 = x2 and y1 < y2.

This article was most recently revised and updated by Michael Ray.