Bertrand Russell
One of the recurring themes in philosophy is the idea that the discipline needs to be given a new methodology. Among empiricists this has often meant making it more scientific. From an early date, Russell enunciated this viewpoint, finding in the techniques of symbolic logic a measure of reassurance that philosophy might be put on a new foundation. Russell did not see the philosopher as merely a logician, however. Symbolic logic might provide the framework for a perfect language, but the content of that language is something else. The job of the philosopher is—for Russell, as it was for Moore—analysis. But the purpose is somewhat different. In most of Russell’s work, analysis has the task of uncovering the assumptions—especially about the kinds of things that exist—that it is necessary to adopt in order to be able to describe the world as it is. For the most part this description is the one that science gives, and it is therefore realistic. Thus, Russell’s use of analysis was openly metaphysical.
There then arises the question of how philosophical analysis—which, at least on one conception, is concerned with how people talk about the world—can presume to give any answers about how the world is. The search for an answer begins with Russell’s theory of descriptions, a doctrine that is evidently closely tied to linguistic concerns.
In a simple subject-predicate statement such as “Socrates is wise,” Russell observed, there seems to be something referred to (Socrates) and something said about it (that he is wise). If the proper name in such a sentence is replaced by a “definite description”—as in the statement “The president of the United States is wise”—there is apparently still something referred to and something said about it. A problem arises, however, when nothing fits the description, as in the statement “The present king of France is bald.” Although there is apparently nothing for the statement to be about, one nevertheless understands what it says. Prior to Russell’s work on definite descriptions, some philosophers—most notably Alexius Meinong (1853–1920)—felt forced by such examples to conclude that, in addition to things that have real existence, there are things that have some other sort of existence, for such statements could not be understood unless there was something for them to be about.
In Russell’s view, philosophers like Meinong had been misled by the surface grammatical form of sentences containing definite descriptions. Although they treated them as if they were simple subject-predicate statements, in reality they were much more complex. Upon analysis, the statement “The present king of France is bald” is shown to be a complex conjunction of other statements. Rendered in symbolic logic, these statements are: (i) (∃x)(Fx), or “There is a present king of France”; (ii) (∀y)(Fy → y=x), or “There is at most one present king of France”; and (iii) (∀x)(Fx → Bx), or “If anyone is a present king of France, he is bald.” More important, each of the three component statements is general, in the sense that it does not refer to anything or anyone in particular. Thus, there is no phrase in the complete analysis equivalent to “the present king of France,” which shows that the phrase is not an expression, like a proper name, that refers to something as the thing that the whole statement is about. There is no need, therefore, to make Meinong’s distinction between things that have real existence and things that have some other kind of existence.
Because descriptions do not refer directly to things in the world, however, there must be some other way in which such a direct connection between language and the world is made. In search of this connection, Russell turned his attention to proper names. The name Aristotle, for example, does not seem to carry any descriptive content. But Russell argues, on the contrary, that ordinary names are really concealed definite descriptions (Aristotle may simply mean “The student of Plato who taught Alexander, wrote the Metaphysics, etc.”). If a name had no descriptive content, one could not sensibly ask about the existence of its bearer, for one could then not understand what is expressed by a statement involving it. If Russell were a name in this sense (without any descriptive content), then merely to understand the statement “Russell exists” or the statement “Russell does not exist” presupposes that one already knows what Russell refers to. But then there cannot be any genuine question about Russell’s existence, for just to understand the question one must know the thing to which the name refers. Ordinary proper names, however—Russell, Homer, Aristotle, and Santa Claus—as Russell pointed out, are such that it makes sense to question the existence of their bearers. Thus, ordinary names must be concealed descriptions and cannot be the means of directly referring to the particular things in the world.
Russell eventually concluded that things in the world can be talked about only through the medium of a special kind of name—in particular, one about which no question can arise whether it names something or not—and he suggested that in English the only possible candidates are the demonstrative pronouns this and that.
At this point in his thinking, Russell shifted from questions about the nature of language to questions about the nature of the world. He asked what sort of thing it is that can be named in the strict logical sense, that can be known and talked about, and from which one can learn about the world. The important restriction was that no question about whether it exists or not can arise. Ordinary physical objects and other people seemed not to fit this requirement.
In his search for something whose existence cannot be questioned, Russell hit upon present experience and, in particular, upon sense data: one can question whether one is really seeing some physical object—whether, for example, there is a desk before one—but one cannot question that one is having visual impressions or sense data. Thus, what a person can name in the strict logical sense and what things in the world he can refer to directly turn out to be elements of his present experience. Russell therefore made a distinction between what can be known by acquaintance and what can be known only by description—i.e., between things whose existence cannot be doubted and things about whose existence, at least theoretically, doubt can be raised. What is novel about Russell’s conclusion is that it was arrived at from a fairly technical analysis of language. To be directly acquainted with something is to be in a position to give it a name in the strict logical sense, and to know something only by description is to know only that there is something that the description uniquely fits.
Russell was not constant in his view about physical objects. At one point he thought that the observer must infer their existence as the best hypothesis to explain the observer’s experience. Later he held that they were “logical constructions” out of sense data.